Source of book: borrowed from the library
“‘cause.”
“‘cause why?”
“Just ‘cause!”
Actually,
that is the way every theory about why there is something rather than
nothing seems to end. At the end of the speculation, there is some fact
that simply must be assumed. (The book refers to them as “brute facts,”
the philosophical term for a fact that does not have an underlying
explanation. Philosophers debate whether “brute facts” can exist or
not.)
Jim
Holt is an author, but also a philosophy major. This book straddles the
lines between science, religion, and philosophy as it explores
contemporary and historical thought about the title question. The existential question.
Why is there something rather than nothing?
Or, as Julian Huxley put it (as quoted in the book):
“The
clear light of science, we are often told, has abolished mystery,
leaving only logic and reason,” Huxley wrote. “This is quite untrue.
Science has removed the obscuring veil of mystery from many phenomena,
much to the benefit of the human race: but it confronts us with a basic
and universal mystery - the mystery of existence...why does the world
exist?”
Holt
starts by laying out the three ways of approaching the question. The
optimist point of view is that there is a reason for the universe, and
we may well discover it. The pessimist point of view is that while there
may be a reason, we probably won’t discover it. The rejectionist view
is that there is no reason for the universe. The universe and the
question are both meaningless.
Since
there wouldn’t be much of a book without the optimist viewpoint, Holt
spends most of the book on various ideas of the reason there is a
universe.
To
that end, the author discusses the ultimate question with a number of
scientists and philosophers, challenging the weaknesses of each
position. Holt’s goal is not to draw a conclusion, but to explore the
question and its potential answers.
Although
this book can be enjoyed by the average educated person, I must say
that it helps to have a working knowledge of philosophy, quantum
mechanics, and string theory. Especially philosophy, since the language
and technique of philosophy permeate the book. I highly recommend the
venerable textbook Socrates to Sartre: A History of Philosophy as a good starting point for neophytes. (It is readily available used for very little cost.)
First
of all, there are some things I found annoying about the book. Pretty
much all of them are to be expected from a philosophy major (and perhaps
philosopher) writing a book of his experiences. The most egregious is
the fact that not one, but two scenes in the book involve the author
sitting in Sartre’s favorite cafe on Paris’ Left Bank, reading. (Hegel
in one case. Surprise. Or not.) Similarly, the book occasionally focuses
too much on what read as set pieces, where he thinks about what he
discussed, while dropping the name of a pretentious wine he is drinking.
(I have a feeling I could easily write like that, so I know the
temptation. I excoriate his editor, however.)
The
other thing which was disappointing (to me at least) is that he
mentions his own philosophy near the beginning, but never goes on to
explain it or how he came to that conclusion. (He says he has adopted a
variation of the gnostic belief that the physical world was created by a
malevolent being, but one that was largely incompetent, thus giving
rise to a world that failed at being the worst possible world.) I am
curious how he came to the conclusion (particularly in light of the rest
of the book.) The only clear clue here is his conversation John Leslie,
in which Leslie posits that of all the possible universes, ours was
pretty far from the most perfect. However, he opined that, “Still, I
think you’d have to go quite far below us to have a world which was not
worth having at all.”
Those flaws notwithstanding, this was an interesting and worthwhile read. Here are a few that stood out to me:
I
did not realize that Edwin Hubble’s theory of an expanding universe
that can be traced back in time to a singularity (colloquially known as
the “Big Bang”) was initially embraced by Christians, particularly
Catholics, as proof of a creator. Or that for the same reason, it was
rabidly hated by atheists. Essentially, the idea of a definite beginning
implied that something (or nothing) existed before that. An eternal,
unchanging universe better suited the premise that there was no need for
a creator.
(Personal
note here: As a theist, I find the idea of creating the world through a
singularity to be great fun. If I could create the universe, I think it
would be a gas to use a tiny pill that would expand to make everything -
kind of like the best of all possible versions of those expanding foam
animals my kids play with. Bang! It would be awesome.)
Also
good was the point made by Heidegger that fear has a definite object.
Anxiety, in contrast, is directed at the unknowable. The nothing, as it
were.
It
was also interesting to be reminded that nearly everything in the
history of philosophy can be traced back to Plato and Aristotle. Despite
all of the scientific advances that have illuminated so much of the
physical world, the two of them asked so many of the great questions -
and answered them in contrasting ways that are reflected in philosophy
throughout the ages.
The
age old ontological proof, first used by Plato in his forms, and best
known, perhaps, as stated by Aquinas, rears its head throughout the book.
But its flaws are also apparent. (As I stated above, everything
boils down to “‘cause!” The competing scientific theories at some point
are reduced to a brute fact as well. Perhaps the laws of the universe
inevitably give rise to a universe. But why are there laws? “‘cause!” Or
perhaps all universes and all laws are possible. But why are they
possible? It all eventually goes to the same place, and one must choose
what seems to be more likely in view of the fact that there does appear
to be a universe, governed by rational and discoverable laws.
Another
strong point of this book was the way the author made his various
interview subjects come to life. Their conversations are a high point of
the book - and much more interesting than the author’s own navel
gazing. For example, the interview with the late John Updike revealed a
man far more fun and human than I would have expected. He sounded rather
delightful to talk to - not always the case with famous authors or
celebrities in general.
Or
his visit to the house of David Deutsch, who a previous journalist
described as “setting international standards of slovenliness.” Holt
adds his own memorable description of it as “experiments in indoor
composting” and (my favorite) “an adventure in high-entropy
housekeeping.” (Some days, my own house could be described as rather
“high-entropy...”)
Holt also gets points from me for his clever use of quotations from The Devil’s Dictionary by the poisonously pithy Ambrose Bierce.
Beyond the stuff that was interesting, thought provoking, or amusing, two additional passages stood out to me.
The
first is the chapter (at the end) devoted to the return to nothingness.
Death. The author’s mother passes as he watches, and he is forced to
confront why death causes us anxiety. Why, after all, can we not make
peace with it? Holt notes that (with a very few exceptions), we can
imagine a time before we were born, but have great difficulty imagining
the universe without us. We understand beginnings, but resist final
ends. Why do we “rage, rage against the dying of the light.”? Or, as
Ecclesiastes puts it, eternity has been placed in the hearts of men.
Holt has no real answers here.
The
second passage is one that I find explains a problem that I have been
struggling with over many years. Holt interviews Richard Swinburne, an
Oxford professor and Eastern Orthodox Christian, (not to be confused
with Algernon Charles Swinburne, the poet) who lays out a case for the
existence of God. In fact, a pretty good defense of the Gospel is given
by Swinburne. I found it interesting that Swinburne came across as
remarkably understated. He didn’t claim that he could prove more than he
could, acknowledged the weaknesses of his arguments, and didn’t
name-call. (A total contrast to Richard Dawkins, the prominent atheist,
who commonly resorts to flame-throwing and name calling rather than
intellectual proof. Holt quotes him at length, and acknowledges that he
is rather a bully.)
The argument made by Swinburne was not revolutionary to my thinking. It built on Aquinas and others, and was interesting.
What
has stayed in my head since reading it, is his explanation for why so
many philosophers violently rejected the concept of God.
“Many
philosophers were brought up in strictly religious households. As
adolescents, they found their religion in conflict with things that were
obviously true, and they rebelled against it. Then later, when someone
shows them a more appealing sort of religion, they’re not going to grasp
it.”
I
have had conversations with a number of friends about why many of my
generation (and the next) have left the Christian faith. This tendency
seems to be particularly strong among those who were raised in strict
environments. (Such as the Christian Patriarchy movement.)
This
explains that, and even more, it explains the struggles that I have had
with my faith and my worldview. It explains why those who suffered
abuse by their parents in the name of Christ have rejected everything.
When
one is told that something is true, when it clearly is utter bullshit,
and then told that one is rebellious for not believing it, it is natural
to reject the entire worldview.
And
then, many within the Church double down by claiming that all those who
reject Christianity do so simply because they prefer to sin. In
addition to being self-righteous, condescending, and cruel, this
statement is false. Obviously false, to anyone who actually has friends
who are Christians-turned-atheist, always-atheist, or even
atheist-turned-Christian. There are many reasons we believe or
disbelieve. Some are intellectual. Some, admittedly, might be moral. But
so many more stem from hurt and pain. To tell the child of an alcoholic
mother who beat him, while all the time pretending to be a perfect
church member that he just “wants to sin” is truly lacking in truth,
understanding, or love.
I’ve
already written about a few of the patently untrue things I was
expected to swallow, and I hope to do more in the coming year.
In
summary, this book has flaws, but it is a worthwhile read. I believe it
is vitally important to understand the arguments on all sides of this
issue, particularly before making moral judgments about the intentions
of those who hold to different viewpoints.