Source of book: Borrowed from the library
Another impulse read from the New Books shelf.
I have a good friend who is a thoughtful guy, and we, from
time to time, have conversations about religion, philosophy, and ethics and
stuff. I recall in particular a conversation from a couple of years back.
At the time, my friend was rather into Christian
Apologetics, specifically William Lane Craig. Unfortunately, I loathe
apologetics in general, and presuppositional
apologetics in particular. While Craig does have some good points, and he
is at least far more intellectually honest than the average
Evangelical/Baptist/Fundamentalist, he still had several things that rubbed me
really wrong. The main one, of course, was Divine Command Theory,
which I find to be essentially ethical suicide. (I might have to blog about
that some time.) In the context of this conversation, however, the big irritant
was Craig’s chauvinism about ethical systems. The presuppositional assumption
is that, without some “objective” source of ethics - meaning a supernatural
being who has laid down the law - there is no possible way to determine right
from wrong in an intellectually consistent manner. And, to the
Evangelical/Baptist/Fundie sorts like Craig, that means acceptance of the bible
as literally dictated, capable
of a single obvious objective interpretation, and so on. Of course, this is
a major flaw in presuppositional apologetics in general: they make the leap
from “there is a rational basis for belief in an ultimate source of the
universe” to “our interpretation of an ancient collection of writings is the
only possible conclusion,” which is ludicrous to anyone who pushes the issue.
Anyway, here is where I am going with this. At some point in
the conversation, my friend raised the question of how one determines ethics
without a divine command. This is a legitimate question, actually, and it is
one that has occupied philosophers around the globe for the last, well, four or
five thousand years at least. That IS one of the great questions of philosophy.
Why are we here? Does life have purpose? And, perhaps most pertinent: How should we live, and why?
At this point in the conversation, my friend brought up the
Utilitarians, with kind of a derogatory tone. Which is precisely how Craig and
other presuppostionalists respond to any
ethical system which does not start with “things are right or wrong because God
says so.”
This was not a surprise. In the circles I was raised, the
Utilitarians were definitely personae non
grata, blamed for every ill of our modern life - well, along with Hegel
and Nietzsche. It was obviously their
fault for the holocaust, Stalin’s purges, and homosexuality. (And every other
possible real or perceived evil.) The claim was that the Utilitarians severed
the connection between ethics and the teachings of the Church, so after that,
anything was ethically permissible.
That this is a ridiculous straw man should be obvious to
anyone with a passing knowledge of philosophy.
I will confess, I didn’t really understand the issues until
relatively later in life. I wasn’t ready in high school to get into the
details. Later, in my late 20s, I did explore things a good bit more, and
realized that it was pretty obvious why the Fundie/Evangelical tradition in
which I was raised as absolutely freaked out about Utilitarianism. (More on this
later.)
At this point, let me give a recommendation: before you read
this book, you really should read an introductory book on philosophy. The
author assumes the reader already knows the outlines of Utilitarian thought, as
well as Plato, Aristotle, Hegel, Marx, Kant, and others. Trying to read this
book without some form of background knowledge is going to be frustrating.
Trust me on this.
So, here is my suggestion: go online and find a copy of Socrates
to Sartre: A History of Philosophy by Samuel Enoch Stumpf. Various
editions have been available for decades - since 1966 - and used copies are
fairly easy to find. A hardback 6th Edition (1999) graces my bookshelf, and I
have referred to it constantly since reading it cover-to-cover. One of the
strengths of the book is that it goes through Western philosophy in
chronological order. It really helped me to see that philosophy isn’t a bunch
of independent schools of thought, but a long conversation stretching back
thousands of years. Each new development is a response and reaction to what
came before. You can’t understand Bentham unless you understand Kant and
Spinoza and Aristotle. Go get this book. Read it. Then come talk philosophy
with me.
Sorry about the long introduction. I thought it might be
helpful in seeing where I was coming from both in my own Fundie history and in
more recent conversations.
Bart Schultz didn’t write a summary of Utilitarian thought,
nor did he intend primarily to defend or criticize Utilitarian philosophy. On the
other hand, this isn’t a mere biography of the four great Utilitarians. Schultz
weaves the biographical information together with a chronological view of how
the ideas of the main characters changed over time. The goal is to let the
lives of the Utilitarians shed light on their writings - to show how the men
(and women) themselves aid in the interpretation of their ideas.
Generally, when one thinks of Utilitarianism, one thinks of
Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. Schultz brings in two other luminaries.
First is William Godwin (perhaps best known these days for being the eventual
husband of Mary Wollstonecraft, author of A
Vindication of the Rights of Woman), but who really set the stage
for what Bentham and Mill did within a few years. Likewise, Schultz spends a
good bit of time on Henry Sidgwick, who took Mill’s ideas even further by the
dawn of the 20th Century. Both of these figures are important, although less
known than Bentham and Mill.
William Godwin, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Henry Sidgwick
Schultz also did something which has been long overdue, which is to consider the
three women whose contributions have been largely suppressed and forgotten
because of a combination of sexism and prejudice against women who refused to
adhere to cultural demands for their gender. In addition to Wollstonecraft (who
was largely dismissed for her child out of wedlock and other sexual liaisons -
stuff Victorian men were expected to
have but women were punished for), there were two others. Harriet Taylor,
Mill’s eventual wife (after perhaps a long affair...it’s complicated, as the
book points out) collaborated on many of his works - she should be listed as a
co-author. Eleanor Balfour - sister of Arthur Balfour, Prime Minister of
England - married Henry Sidgwick, and was a significant influence on his philosophy
throughout his life. She too likely deserves a co-author credit for his works.
Mary Wollstonecraft, Harriet Taylor Mill, Eleanor Sidgwick
The common factor that these women had is that they were all
independent, feminist, and progressive - in an era when this was frowned upon.
Men might perhaps be radical, but women were expected to know their place,
submit to their husbands, and keep their vaginas virginal. These three, um,
perhaps not so much. But, as Schultz points out, it is often their contributions to philosophy that
have aged the best. It is difficult to escape the conclusion that it was these
women who were most ahead of their time, not just on questions of sex and
gender - but on racism, colonialism, and poverty as well. More so than their
husbands, they would seem at home in our 21st Century world.
This is a long book, and a dense one. Small print, lots of
pages, footnotes, and a plethora of quotes from the subjects and others. It
took me a while for that reason. It was quite excellent, however.
Let me try to hit a few highlights, realizing that I will
miss so many great lines, quotes, and ideas.
First, let me start with this:
The Utilitarians have
been largely slandered and intentionally misunderstood by the reactionary
forces in my religious tradition.
Certainly, they have been unjustly mocked for attempting to
apply scientific reasoning and reason to the difficult questions of personal -
and political - ethics. I think, actually, that this is the reason they have been slandered. At
their best, the Utilitarians presented a formidable intellectual and ethical
threat to the status quo. The challenged the idea that noble birth entitled one
to luxury while others starved. They questioned whether something could be
“virtuous” in the abstract, without reference to how it affected others. They raised
doubts about church teachings on sexuality, and insisted that “because
tradition says so” was insufficient to determine right and wrong.
I think, too, that Utilitarianism has been limited in the
popular imagination to a mere individualistic ethical system. Certainly the
Utilitarians did examine how each of
us individually might approach
ethics. But that was less of a concern than the political question: how should public policy be shaped? And this is
where, in my view (and many others), the most lasting contribution of
Utilitarian thought is manifest.
At its core, then, Utilitarianism asks that we order our
politics (and our own actions) with the view to maximize “happiness” and - and
this is crucial - minimize pointless suffering.
Two points need to be made here. First, “happiness” in the
Utilitarian sense - and in the sense intended in our own Declaration of
Independence, the “pursuit of happiness,” isn’t some fleeting,
circumstance-based, subjective feeling of pleasantness. Rather, “happiness”
means well being, a decent life, a lack of needless suffering. For Jefferson, this meant that it was a god-given right for
each of us to pursue well being, a lack of pointless and unneeded suffering.
The American Dream, if you will. (Really, the dream of humanity.) So, for the
Utilitarians, the goal was to attain this well being, lack of suffering, and
good, decent life...for everyone, not
just the wealthy.
The second point is this: the goal of Utilitarianism was in
large part to avoid policies which inflicted needless and pointless suffering
on people. In considering our own actions - and our public policies - we need
to consider whether we will harm others. For the same reason, something which
benefits a few wealthy powerful people while causing harm to the poor is an ethical evil. In this sense,
Utilitarianism is actually rather similar to the teachings of Christ - the ones
that modern Evangelicals are thoroughly committed to ignoring in our time.
Utilitarianism is “love your neighbor” in action, in that sense. The author
also quotes Socrates on this point: “Actions are more reliable evidence than
words.”
I cannot emphasize enough the importance of the political in
this book. Let’s start with this quote from William Godwin (who is the first
subject in this book) from Political
Justice:
“Is it well, that so large a part of
the community should be kept in abject penury, rendered stupid with ignorance,
and disgustful with vice, perpetuated in nakedness and hunger, goaded to the
commission of crimes, and made victims to merciless laws which the rich have
instituted to oppress them? Is it sedition to enquire whether this state of
things may not be exchanged for a better?”
Couldn’t this have been written in our own time? It sure
continues to ring true in an era when the idea that the wealthy of society owe
the rest of us something is somehow controversial. We have lost the ability to
recognize inequality as oppression - something the biblical prophets had no
difficulty doing.
I will note in the above, the dedication to education. This
was certainly a common theme for the utilitarians. Women, the poor, and
(nearly) everyone should have an
education, they believed. One can directly trace the thought from here to John
Dewey and others who pushed for a universal public education. It is no
exaggeration to say that Godwin, Bentham, and Mill deserve much of the credit
for the fact that humanity (particularly in the first world) is more literate
than any time in history.
I’ll note at this point an interesting question regarding
Bentham. Of all the Utilitarians, he was the most prosaic, having little of the
sense of wonder and magic that the artistic sorts would have. (Sidgwick, on the
other hand, was a friend and devotee of Tennyson,
and was poetic as heck.) The author, however, points out that Bentham’s views
on education needing to be more about usefulness to the student than cultural
indoctrination were more a reaction to the teaching of subservience than
contempt for poetry.
Bentham had particular contempt for the role of religion in
society - and I am afraid in the era of Trump, I am increasingly of Bentham’s
viewpoint on that. Like Bentham, I find that organized religion in our time and
his is so far divorced from the teachings and example of Christ as to be
unrecognizable. And, furthermore, that it is calculated and focused on
justifying injustice and oppression. Here is one quote that stuck with me:
“Destitute of intellectual instruction,
man, even in the bosom of the most civilized country, is often found appearing
in no better a character than that of a savage. Of the Hulks, and the Penal
Colonies - not to speak of the home Prisons - the population is, for the most
part, composed of human beings thus abandoned to ignorance, vice, and
wretchedness. Such as to the far greater part, appears to be the state of the
population under the Church of England.”
Every bit as devastating is Bentham’s observation that
religion spends an awful lot of time convincing people to hate things they
would not otherwise hate. In our own time (as in Benthams...this is also a
theme of the Utilitarians), this includes the endless obsession with sex and
genitals and what people do with them.
Mill too was no fan of established religion. He too argued
that the poor should have a right to an education - but not by the Church of
England, which spent its time trying to convince the poor that they deserved
poverty.
I also found interesting Mill’s intellectual crisis, where
he felt he needed to somehow revise his views to accommodate the reality he had
discovered. (I’m not even going to attempt an explanation - you’ll have to read
the book.) The one thing that jumped out at me was the argument - still ongoing
today - about how much of our morality is merely an artifact of evolutionary
“survival value” versus things that have an inherent “moral value” in and of
themselves, separate from evolutionary utility.
While the classic Utilitarians definitely show the defects
of the age in which they lived, they had some great ideas which have been
influential today. Chief among them was a radical (for their time) feminism. I
would also add a shockingly progressive view of poverty and economics. Both of
these seem, to me, to be a solid stand in favor of Christ’s teaching, against
the forces of Empire and hierarchy.
One of the most interesting parts of the book in regard to
feminism was the discussion of Harriet Taylor Mill. Harriet was widely
slandered as a shrew and haridan during her lifetime, and later by the
biographers of John Stuart Mill. Her contributions to their books were
dismissed, and every fault amplified.
However, as later biographers noticed, she really wasn’t
like that. The problem was, she failed and/or refused to be a good Victorian
woman. Her marriage to John Taylor was troubled, and, despite the fact she bore
him three children, it was difficult at best. Reading between the lines of her writing
(with Mill) on domestic violence and divorce, there is good reason to believe
he was abusive to her. Eventually, they would separate, although the would, of
necessity, remain legally married. Her intellectual collaboration with John
Stuart Mill was apparently a huge
scandal, despite a lack of evidence of sexual intimacy. (Indeed, there is
reason to believe he was impotent.) Rather, the idea that a woman might be
merely a friend without benefits was rather unthinkable. On the other hand,
there was definitely an emotional connection. After Taylor’s death, they did eventually marry.
Her’s was a “complicated” life by female Victorian standards. And, she wrote
extensively with a distrust for “conventional” marriage. As a later biographer
would explain:
“Finding a way to construct such a life
took consummate skill in a society that disallowed divorce, prevented married
women from maintaining financial independence, and discouraged women from
obtaining a liberal arts education.”
The same biographer would also note a fundamental hypocrisy
of Victorian society. And, let’s be honest, of our own as well:
“Selflessness is the kind of virtue
society tries to instill in women. (Men tend to be hypocrites on this score,
since they are allowed some freedom for their own desires, while women wound
their wings at every attempt to expand them against their gilded bars.”
Harriet’s influence on Mill is readily apparent in their
mutual work, On the Subjection of Women.
I really wanted to quote several pages that were reproduced in this book. Let
the following suffice, as a cogent description of the effects of social pressure
on women to be a certain way. This pressure makes it difficult to ascertain
exactly what the differences are (if any) between the sexes.
“All causes, social and natural,
combine to make it unlikely that women should be collectively rebellious to the
power of men. They are so far in a position different from all other subject
classes, that their masters require something more from them than actual
service. Men do not want solely the obedience of women, they want their
sentiments. All men, except the most brutish, desire to have, in the woman most
nearly connected with them, not a forced slave, but a willing one, not a slave
merely, but a favourite. They have therefore put everything in practice to
enslave their minds. The masters of all other slaves rely, for maintaining
obedience, on fear; either fear of themselves, or religious fears. The masters
of women wanted more than simple obedience, and they turned the whole force of
education to effect their belief that their ideal of character is the very
opposite to that of men; not self-will, and government by self-control, but
submission, and yielding to the control of others. All the moralities tell them
that it is the duty of women, and all the current sentimentalities that it is
their nature, to live for others; to make complete abnegation of themselves,
and to have no life but in their affections. And by their affections are meant
the only ones they are allowed to have - those to the men with whom they are
connected, or to the children who constitute an additional and indefeasible tie
between them and a man. When we put together three things - first, the natural
attraction between opposite sexes; secondly, the wife’s entire dependence on
the husband, every privilege or pleasure she has being either his gift, or
depending entirely on his will; and lastly, that the principal object of human
pursuit, consideration, and all objects of social ambition, can in general be
sought or obtained by her only through him, it would be a miracle if the object
of being attractive to men had not become the polar star of feminine education
and formation of character. And, this great means of influence over the minds
of women having been acquired, an instinct of selfishness made men avail
themselves of it to the utmost as a means of holding women in subjection, by
representing to them meekness, submissiveness, and resignation of all
individual will into the hands of a man, as an essential part of sexual
attractiveness. Can it be doubted that any of the other yokes which mankind
have succeeded in breaking, would have subsisted till now if the same means had
existed, and had been as sedulously used, to bow down their minds to it?”
Damn mic drop after that one. And it gets even better:
“Stand on the ground of common sense
and the constitution of the human mind, I deny that any one knows, or can
know, the nature of the two sexes, as long as they have only been seen in their
present relation to one another. If men had ever been found in society without
women, or women without men, or if there had been a society of men and women in
which the women were not under the control of the men, something might have
been positively know about the mental and moral differences which may be
inherent in the nature of each. What is now called the nature of women is an
eminently artificial thing - the result of forced repression in some
directions, unnatural stimulation in others. It may be asserted without
scruple, that no other class of dependents have had their character so entirely
distorted from its natural proportions by their relation with their masters…”
It’s as if Mill had viewed the toxic teachings of the Fundie
cults my wife and I spent time in - or sat through a 21st Century Evangelical
sermon on gender essentialism. Oh yes, this is one reason we left and will
never go back. The Utilitarians argued for women’s suffrage, among other
feminist causes. I believe this is one of the biggest reasons why Fundies
loathe them, and have grossly slandered them.
Now, let’s take a look at the Utilitarian approach to
poverty. Again, here it is helpful to see Utilitarianism as a reaction against
other ideas. I have mixed feelings about Edmund Burke, but I will grant that
his ideas were in direct reaction to the French Revolution. And he has some
great points. He identified why people like me, who are essentially
center-right in temperament and philosophy, have a distaste for revolution,
preferring reform. And also why we are deeply concerned about the modern
American Right, which combines a Gilded
Age approach to inequality with a vicious racism. Burke had his weaknesses,
though, and it is best to view the Utilitarian approach to poverty and
economics as a reaction to the worst of Burke, rather than a confirmation of
Marx. (Indeed, the Utilitarians had a bias toward individual freedom, rather
than government control, in many cases.) Likewise, the Utilitarians were in
conversation with Adam Smith - who was far
less libertarian or social darwinist than the modern disciples of Ayn Rand
would have you believe.
So, for the Utilitarians, it was natural to question whether
the status quo was ethical - or inevitable. Mill wrote in his biography a
number of statements on economics which I found fascinating and pertinent to
our own modern discussion. First, Mill questions a conflation of free
enterprise with oppression of labor. And credits Harriet with the idea, by the
way.
“This tone [of Harriet’s] consisted chiefly
in making the proper distinction between the laws of the production of Wealth,
which are real laws of nature, dependent on the properties of objects, and the
modes of its Distribution, which, subject to certain conditions, depend on
human will. The common run of political economists confuse these
together, under the designation of economic laws, which they deem incapable of
being defeated or modified by human effort; ascribing the same necessity to
things dependent on the unchangeable conditions of our earthly existence, and
to those which, being but the necessary consequences of particular social
arrangement, are merely coextensive with these. Give certain institutions and
customs, wages, profits, and rent will be determined by certain causes; but this
class of political economists drop the indispensable presupposition, and argue
that these causes must by an inherent necessity, against which no human means
can avail, determine the shares which fall, in the division of the produce, to
labourers, capitalists, and landlords.”
Again, a mic drop moment. I had a conversation just today
with a doctrinaire right-winger who seemed to insist that there was no possible
way to change the allocation of wealth and income. Economic laws (which largely
benefited him) were fixed, and human efforts to change things were doomed to
failure - and would indeed fuck up the economy at large. Meaning - Always Cut
Taxes™. No matter what the circumstance. Mill (Harriet, really) point out what
should be obvious: there is no inevitability about landlords and capitalists
reaping the vast majority - and growing share - of the production of an
economy. It isn’t the result of immutable laws. It is the result of particular
customs, laws, and institutions. And these can be changed.
Later, Mill makes another fantastic argument. I wish I could
quote it in full, but it is too long. Here is the best of it:
“What is true is, that wages might be
so high as to leave no profit to the capitalist, or not enough to compensate
him for the anxieties and risks of trade; and in that case labourers would be
killing the goose to get at the eggs. And, again, wages might be so low as to
diminish the numbers or impair the working powers of the labourers, and in that
case the capitalist would generally be a loser.”
This much is actually classic Adam Smith. There is a gap
here, however, as Mill points out. Smith calls this the “higgling of the
market.” Mill notes that, given powerful employers, and individual workers,
wages will be at the bottom end of this. Unionized labor would push wages
toward the higher. Realistically, as Mill notes, sometimes mistakes are made,
and the limits on both ends are violated, making adjustments necessary. But
Mill makes a moral judgment, which I not only agree with, but believe is at the
heart of the evil of the present-day right.
“But, having regard to the greatly
superior numbers of the labouring class, and the inevitable scantiness of the
remuneration afforded by even the highest rate of wages which, in the present
state of the arts of production, could possibly become general; whoever does
not wish that the labourers may prevail, and that the highest limit, whatever
it may be, may be attained, must have a standard of morals, and a conception of
the most desirable state of society, widely different from those...of the
present writer.”
Exactly. This is a key point of Utilitarian politics: the
goal should be greater happiness for the greatest number, not a high level of
happiness for the elite few, and misery for everyone else. That this is the
polar opposite to today’s American Right is pretty much beyond dispute. Rather,
they are convinced that employers need ever-increasing power of workers. It’s a
totally different standard of morals than I have. I hate to say that, as I am inclined toward
conservatism. But that isn’t a value of today’s right - they have sold their
souls to Ayn Rand’s philosophy which is that the capitalists deserve as much as
they can squeeze out of everyone else.
Speaking of Adam Smith, how about this from The Wealth of Nations:
“No society can surely be
flourishing and happy, of which the far greater part of the members are poor
and miserable.”
That sounds practically Marxist in comparison with today’s
Right.
In each section, Schultz examines the legacy of each
Utilitarian. After all, philosophy is a continuing conversation, not a set of
boxes containing separate philosophies. As a general rule, I am not a
particular fan of Peter Singer (although he has the occasional good point.) I
tend toward Martha Nussbaum, and her application of Utilitarianism to a modern
world. One particularly fantastic section in the book is the one in which
Nussbaum expounds on Mill’s views of patriotism. I have
written a bit about that. Both Mill and Nussbaum have amazing things to say
on the topic - things which are so relevant today, in a time when the American
Right stands in opposition to Mill’s ideals.
“I never said that we should not have a
particular love of and attachment to our own nation...I compared our relation
to our country to our relationship with our own children: just as good parents
love their children more, but still, compatibly with that, may and should seek
a nation in which all children have decent life-opportunities, so too we may
love our own nation more while seeking a world in which all citizens have
decent life-opportunities.”
AMEN! Is it really that hard? Apparently so to the Steve
Kings of the world, who throw shade on “other people’s babies,” thus setting
themselves up for hell. (Nope, tired of sugarcoating this one. I don’t believe
in the traditional Evangelical hell - but I believe that if it exists, the
overwhelming majority of white Evangelicals right now are competing to purchase
a one-way ticket there. Seriously. Read Matthew 25 again.)
Before I finish, I really should mention the Utilitarians
and sexuality. I believe this is another reason why the Fundies I grew up with
hated them. They dared to challenge the misogyny that underlies “traditional”
sexual rules. In addition to the feminist ideas that women were not the chattel
of men, and should be able to choose their partners - and divorce if they
wished - the Utilitarians pushed back against another trend in the culture.
Jeremy Bentham was the first Utilitarian to question the
proscription of homosexuality. From his point of view, both the risk of
overpopulation and the idea of human freedom indicated that this might be
legitimately questioned. It wasn’t just Bentham, however. By the time of Henry
Sidgwick, there was a full-on puritanical witch hunt under way. The Criminal
Law Amendment Act in England
was a mixed bag, to be honest. (Seriously, note that raping a 10-13 year old
was a misdemeanor - and the Act didn’t do much to fix that.) The main issue,
however, was a re-criminalization of homosexual contact, even when anal
intercourse couldn’t be proved. This is the law that put Oscar
Wilde in prison, and led eventually to his death. The late-Victorian witch
hunt against LGBTQ people is pretty obvious, both in England
and in America.
It coincided with a reaction against Feminism and social change in general.
Hey! Sounds like today too!
There is a fun passage in this book on Sidgwick and his
associates. He was part of “The Apostles,” an intellectual group that included
Tennyson among others. A number of gay men were part of the group, and
Sidgwick, however sympathetic, did his best to censor the erotic or
philosophical writings of these men (particularly John Symonds)
out of a fear it could get them prosecuted. Symonds probably originated the
idea of sexual orientation as we know it now, and the Utilitarians examined the
issue using reason, rather than religious teachings - yet another reason why
Fundies hate them…
One not-so-pleasant part of this book is the examination of
the racism of the Utilitarians. This is, alas, a common experience in reading
about pretty much any Victorians. The Empire was considered noble, and
non-Europeans lesser humans at best. I wish I could say that this was unique,
but it wasn’t. It is difficult to find any white writer of the era that didn’t
share the prejudice and blind spot. Although all of the Utilitarians suffered
from this problem, it was particularly sad to see that Sidgwick, who was the
latest in time and the most prone to doubt about his ideas, was enthusiastic
about Charles Henry Pearson, who pretty openly advocated for genocide of
non-whites. (On a related note, Pearson would fit right in with Steve Bannon, Stephen Miller, and Steve King. And,
sadly, Hitler a half century later. Just vicious racism and a view of whites as
superior. All too familiar…)
Again, this isn’t unique to the Utilitarians. It is a
problem the vast majority of Victorian whites suffered from - it is the rule,
not the exception. But, on the other hand, they did pretty universally deplore
slavery - even before it was cool. The Utilitarians advocated for universal
education, universal suffrage, and human freedom and thriving, before such
concerns became mainstream. In our own era, we owe a lot to the Utilitarians that we don’t even realize. I have been
struck this year with just how much of the modern American Right is actually a
reaction against Utilitarian values. A reaction against a belief that
government should be for the common good, not just the good of the wealthy few.
A reaction against Feminism. A reaction against the egalitarian impulse in general.
At its core, Utilitarianism is about the common good. It is
about considering the needs of others and rejecting selfishness. These are
values in short supply these days.
Let me close, however, with a line from the author’s
epilogue:
“Arguably, if today we were to follow
the lead of the great utilitarians, a decent education for all would be more of
a priority, and the world would be less cruel.”
I cannot agree more.
Having engaged in many discussions of a certain nature on the internet, I think the problem fundies and other similar people have with utilitarianism is even more basic than the issues you mentioned above.
ReplyDeleteUtilitarianism is concerned with consequences. In a very basic and important way, it consists of the question: "Yes, but does it work?"
Fundies hate that. To question is bad, because questioning is doubt, and doubt is crimethink. But even worse, if one asks such a question, sometimes the answer is, "No, it doesn't work."
No, traditional gender roles don't work.
No, Ayn Rand economic policies don't work.
And so on.
Many ethical systems favored by fundies and their fellow travelers are attempts to hermetically seal away their rules from empirical investigation. The rules are the rules, and if they produce suffering and misery...Well, they're good for us, because shut up.
I've taken the attitude if someone refuses to say how their views could be empirically voided, its because they're frightened their ideas and authority are too weak to stand up to scrutiny.
That's an outstanding observation. I certainly have gotten quite a bit of blowback when I have suggested that "does it work" is a necessary question.
DeleteAs you note as well, when you hermetically seal your believes away from reality, no growth can happen. It just becomes an ever more aggressive defense of the indefensible.